|
Bertrand Russell: The Problems of Philosophy

Chapter 13
Knowledge, Error And Probable Opinion
The question as to what we mean by truth and falsehood, which we considered
in the preceding chapter, is of much less interest than the question as
to how we can know what is true and what is false. This question will occupy
us in the present chapter. There can be no doubt that some of our
beliefs are erroneous; thus we are led to inquire what certainty we can
ever have that such and such a belief is not erroneous. In other words,
can we ever know anything at all, or do we merely sometimes by good
luck believe what is true? Before we can attack this question, we must,
however, first decide what we mean by 'knowing', and this question is not
so easy as might be supposed.
At first sight we might imagine that knowledge could be defined as 'true
belief'. When what we believe is true, it might be supposed that we had
achieved a knowledge of what we believe. But this would not accord with
the way in which the word is commonly used. To take a very trivial instance:
If a man believes that the late Prime Minister's last name began with a
B, he believes what is true, since the late Prime Minister was Sir Henry
Campbell Bannerman. But if he believes that Mr. Balfour was the late Prime
Minister, he will still believe that the late Prime Minister's last name
began with a B, yet this belief, though true, would not be thought to constitute
knowledge. If a newspaper, by an intelligent anticipation, announces the
result of a battle before any telegram giving the result has been received,
it may by good fortune announce what afterwards turns out to be the right
result, and it may produce belief in some of its less experienced readers.
But in spite of the truth of their belief, they cannot be said to have
knowledge. Thus it is clear that a true belief is not knowledge when it
is deduced from a false belief.
In like manner, a true belief cannot be called knowledge when it is
deduced by a fallacious process of reasoning, even if the premisses from
which it is deduced are true. If I know that all Greeks are men and that
Socrates was a man, and I infer that Socrates was a Greek, I cannot be
said to know that Socrates was a Greek, because, although my premisses
and my conclusion are true, the conclusion does not follow from the premisses.
But are we to say that nothing is knowledge except what is validly deduced
from true premisses? Obviously we cannot say this. Such a definition is
at once too wide and too narrow. In the first place, it is too wide, because
it is not enough that our premisses should be true, they must also
be known. The man who believes that Mr. Balfour was the late Prime
Minister may proceed to draw valid deductions from the true premiss that
the late Prime Minister's name began with a B, but he cannot be said to
know the conclusions reached by these deductions. Thus we shall
have to amend our definition by saying that knowledge is what is validly
deduced from known premisses. This, however, is a circular definition:
it assumes that we already know what is meant by 'known premisses'. It
can, therefore, at best define one sort of knowledge, the sort we call
derivative, as opposed to intuitive knowledge. We may say: 'Derivative
knowledge is what is validly deduced from premisses known intuitively'.
In this statement there is no formal defect, but it leaves the definition
of intuitive knowledge still to seek.
Leaving on one side, for the moment, the question of intuitive knowledge,
let us consider the above suggested definition of derivative knowledge.
The chief objection to it is that it unduly limits knowledge. It constantly
happens that people entertain a true belief, which has grown up in them
because of some piece of intuitive knowledge from which it is capable of
being validly inferred, but from which it has not, as a matter of fact,
been inferred by any logical process.
Take, for example, the beliefs produced by reading. If the newspapers
announce the death of the King, we are fairly well justified in believing
that the King is dead, since this is the sort of announcement which would
not be made if it were false. And we are quite amply justified in believing
that the newspaper asserts that the King is dead. But here the intuitive
knowledge upon which our belief is based is knowledge of the existence
of sense-data derived from looking at the print which gives the news. This
knowledge scarcely rises into consciousness, except in a person who cannot
read easily. A child may be aware of the shapes of the letters, and pass
gradually and painfully to a realization of their meaning. But anybody
accustomed to reading passes at once to what the letters mean, and is not
aware, except on reflection, that he has derived this knowledge from the
sense-data called seeing the printed letters. Thus although a valid inference
from the letters to their meaning is possible, and could be performed
by the reader, it s not in fact performed, since he does not in fact perform
any operation which can be called logical inference. Yet it would be absurd
to say that the reader does not know that the newspaper announces
the King's death.
We must, therefore, admit as derivative knowledge whatever is the result
of intuitive knowledge even if by mere association, provided there is
a valid logical connexion, and the person in question could become aware
of this connexion by reflection. There are in fact many ways, besides logical
inference, by which we pass from one belief to another: the passage from
the print to its meaning illustrates these ways. These ways may be called
'psychological inference'. We shall, then, admit such psychological inference
as a means of obtaining derivative knowledge, provided there is a discoverable
logical inference which runs parallel to the psychological inference. This
renders our definition of derivative knowledge less precise than we could
wish, since the word 'discoverable' is vague: it does not tell us how much
reflection may be needed in order to make the discovery. But in fact 'knowledge'
is not a precise conception: it merges into 'probable opinion', as we shall
see more fully in the course of the present chapter. A very precise definition,
therefore, should not be sought, since any such definition must be more
or less misleading.
The chief difficulty in regard to knowledge, however, does not arise
over derivative knowledge, but over intuitive knowledge. So long as we
are dealing with derivative knowledge, we have the test of intuitive knowledge
to fall back upon. But in regard to intuitive beliefs, it is by no means
easy to discover any criterion by which to distinguish some as true and
others as erroneous. In this question it is scarcely possible to reach
any very precise result: all our knowledge of truths is infected with some
degree of doubt, and a theory which ignored this fact would be plainly
wrong. Something may be done, however, to mitigate the difficulties of
the question.
Our theory of truth, to begin with, supplies the possibility of distinguishing
certain truths as self-evident in a sense which ensures infallibility.
When a belief is true, we said, there is a corresponding fact, in which
the several objects of the belief form a single complex. The belief is
said to constitute knowledge of this fact, provided it fulfils those
further somewhat vague conditions which we have been considering in the
present chapter. But in regard to any fact, besides the knowledge constituted
by belief, we may also have the kind of knowledge constituted by perception
(taking this word in its widest possible sense). For example, if you know
the hour of the sunset, you can at that hour know the fact that the sun
is setting: this is knowledge of the fact by way of knowledge of truths;
but you can also, if the weather is fine, look to the west and actually
see the setting sun: you then know the same fact by the way of knowledge
of things.
Thus in regard to any complex fact, there are, theoretically, two ways
in which it may be known: (1) by means of a judgement, in which its several
parts are judged to be related as they are in fact related; (2) by means
of acquaintance with the complex fact itself, which may (in a large
sense) be called perception, though it is by no means confined to objects
of the senses. Now it will be observed that the second way of knowing a
complex fact, the way of acquaintance, is only possible when there really
is such a fact, while the first way, like all judgement, is liable to error.
The second way gives us the complex whole, and is therefore only possible
when its parts do actually have that relation which makes them combine
to form such a complex. The first way, on the contrary, gives us the parts
and the relation severally, and demands only the reality of the parts and
the relation: the relation may not relate those parts in that way, and
yet the judgement may occur.
It will be remembered that at the end of Chapter XI we suggested that
there might be two kinds of self-evidence, one giving an absolute guarantee
of truth, the other only a partial guarantee. These two kinds can now be
distinguished.
We may say that a truth is self-evident, in the first and most absolute
sense, when we have acquaintance with the fact which corresponds to the
truth. When Othello believes that Desdemona loves Cassio, the corresponding
fact, if his belief were true, would be 'Desdemona's love for Cassio'.
This would be a fact with which no one could have acquaintance except Desdemona;
hence in the sense of self-evidence that we are considering, the truth
that Desdemona loves Cassio (if it were a truth) could only be self-evident
to Desdemona. All mental facts, and all facts concerning sense-data, have
this same privacy: there is only one person to whom they can be self-evident
in our present sense, since there is only one person who can be acquainted
with the mental things or the sense-data concerned. Thus no fact about
any particular existing thing can be self-evident to more than one person.
On the other hand, facts about universals do not have this privacy. Many
minds may be acquainted with the same universals; hence a relation between
universals may be known by acquaintance to many different people. In all
cases where we know by acquaintance a complex fact consisting of certain
terms in a certain relation, we say that the truth that these terms are
so related has the first or absolute kind of self-evidence, and in these
cases the judgement that the terms are so related must be true.
Thus this sort of self-evidence is an absolute guarantee of truth.
But although this sort of self-evidence is an absolute guarantee of
truth, it does not enable us to be absolutely certain, in the case
of any given judgement, that the judgement in question is true. Suppose
we first perceive the sun shining, which is a complex fact, and thence
proceed to make the judgement 'the sun is shining'. In passing from the
perception to the judgement, it is necessary to analyse the given complex
fact: we have to separate out 'the sun' and 'shining' as constituents of
the fact. In this process it is possible to commit an error; hence even
where a fact has the first or absolute kind of self-evidence, a
judgement believed to correspond to the fact is not absolutely infallible,
because it may not really correspond to the fact. But if it does correspond
(in the sense explained in the preceding chapter), then it must be true.
The second sort of self-evidence will be that which belongs to judgements
in the first instance, and is not derived from direct perception of a fact
as a single complex whole. This second kind of self-evidence will have
degrees, from the very highest degree down to a bare inclination in favour
of the belief. Take, for example, the case of a horse trotting away from
us along a hard road. At first our certainty that we hear the hoofs is
complete; gradually, if we listen intently, there comes a moment when we
think perhaps it was imagination or the blind upstairs or our own heartbeats;
at last we become doubtful whether there was any noise at all; then we
think we no longer hear anything, and at last we know we
no longer hear anything. In this process, there is a continual gradation
of self-evidence, from the highest degree to the least, not in the sense-data
themselves, but in the judgements based on them.
Or again: Suppose we are comparing two shades of colour, one blue and
one green. We can be quite sure they are different shades of colour; but
if the green colour is gradually altered to be more and more like the blue,
becoming first a blue-green, then a greeny-blue, then blue, there will
come a moment when we are doubtful whether we can see any difference, and
then a moment when we know that we cannot see any difference. The same
thing happens in tuning a musical instrument, or in any other case where
there is a continuous gradation. Thus self-evidence of this sort is a matter
of degree; and it seems plain that the higher degrees are more to be trusted
than the lower degrees.
In derivative knowledge our ultimate premisses must have some degree
of self-evidence, and so must their connexion with the conclusions deduced
from them. Take for example a piece of reasoning in geometry. It is not
enough that the axioms from which we start should be self-evident: it is
necessary also that, at each step in the reasoning, the connexion of premiss
and conclusion should be self-evident. In difficult reasoning, this connexion
has often only a very small degree of self-evidence; hence errors of reasoning
are not improbable where the difficulty is great.
From what has been said it is evident that, both as regards intuitive
knowledge and as regards derivative knowledge, if we assume that intuitive
knowledge is trustworthy in proportion to the degree of its self-evidence,
there will be a gradation in trustworthiness, from the existence of noteworthy
sense-data and the simpler truths of logic and arithmetic, which may be
taken as quite certain, down to judgements which seem only just more probable
than their opposites. What we firmly believe, if it is true, is called
knowledge, provided it is either intuitive or inferred (logically
or psychologically) from intuitive knowledge from which it follows logically.
What we firmly believe, if it is not true, is called error. What
we firmly believe, if it is neither knowledge nor error, and also what
we believe hesitatingly, because it is, or is derived from, something which
has not the highest degree of self-evidence, may be called probable
opinion. Thus the greater part of what would commonly pass as knowledge
is more or less probable opinion.
In regard to probable opinion, we can derive great assistance from coherence,
which we rejected as the definition of truth, but may often use
as a criterion. A body of individually probable opinions, if they
are mutually coherent, become more probable than any one of them would
be individually. It is in this way that many scientific hypotheses acquire
their probability. They fit into a coherent system of probable opinions,
and thus become more probable than they would be in isolation. The same
thing applies to general philosophical hypotheses. Often in a single case
such hypotheses may seem highly doubtful, while yet, when we consider the
order and coherence which they introduce into a mass of probable opinion,
they become pretty nearly certain. This applies, in particular, to such
matters as the distinction between dreams and waking life. If our dreams,
night after night, were as coherent one with another as our days, we should
hardly know whether to believe the dreams or the waking life. As it is,
the test of coherence condemns the dreams and confirms the waking life.
But this test, though it increases probability where it is successful,
never gives absolute certainty, unless there is certainty already at some
point in the coherent system. Thus the mere organization of probable opinion
will never, by itself, transform it into indubitable knowledge.
|