|
Bertrand Russell: The Problems of Philosophy

Chapter 14
The Limits Of Philosophical Knowledge
In all that we have said hitherto concerning philosophy, we have scarcely
touched on many matters that occupy a great space in the writings of most
philosophers. Most philosophers -- or, at any rate, very many -- profess
to be able to prove, by a priori metaphysical reasoning, such things
as the fundamental dogmas of religion, the essential rationality of the
universe, the illusoriness of matter, the unreality of all evil, and so
on. There can be no doubt that the hope of finding reason to believe such
theses as these has been the chief inspiration of many life-long students
of philosophy. This hope, I believe, is vain. It would seem that knowledge
concerning the universe as a whole is not to be obtained by metaphysics,
and that the proposed proofs that, in virtue of the laws of logic such
and such things must exist and such and such others cannot, are
not capable of surviving a critical scrutiny. In this chapter we shall
briefly consider the kind of way in which such reasoning is attempted,
with a view to discovering whether we can hope that it may be valid.
The great representative, in modern times, of the kind of view which
we wish to examine, was Hegel (1770-1831). Hegel's philosophy is very difficult,
and commentators differ as to the true interpretation of it. According
to the interpretation I shall adopt, which is that of many, if not most,
of the commentators and has the merit of giving an interesting and important
type of philosophy, his main thesis is that everything short of the Whole
is obviously fragmentary, and obviously incapable of existing without the
complement supplied by the rest of the world. Just as a comparative anatomist,
from a single bone, sees what kind of animal the whole must have been,
so the metaphysician, according to Hegel, sees, from any one piece of reality,
what the whole of reality must be -- at least in its large outlines. Every
apparently separate piece of reality has, as it were, hooks which grapple
it to the next piece; the next piece, in turn, has fresh hooks, and so
on, until the whole universe is reconstructed. This essential incompleteness
appears, according to Hegel, equally in the world of thought and in the
world of things. In the world of thought, if we take any idea which is
abstract or incomplete, we find, on examination, that if we forget its
incompleteness, we become involved in contradictions; these contradictions
turn the idea in question into its opposite, or antithesis; and in order
to escape, we have to find a new, less incomplete idea, which is the synthesis
of our original idea and its antithesis. This new idea, though less incomplete
than the idea we started with, will be found, nevertheless, to be still
not wholly complete, but to pass into its antithesis, with which it must
be combined in a new synthesis. In this way Hegel advances until he reaches
the 'Absolute Idea', which, according to him, has no incompleteness, no
opposite, and no need of further development. The Absolute Idea, therefore,
is adequate to describe Absolute Reality; but all lower ideas only describe
ality as it appears to a partial view, not as it is to one who simultaneously
surveys the Whole. Thus Hegel reaches the conclusion that Absolute Reality
forms one single harmonious system, not in space or time, not in any degree
evil, wholly rational, and wholly spiritual. Any appearance to the contrary,
in the world we know, can be proved logically -- so he believes -- to be
entirely due to our fragmentary piecemeal view of the universe. If we saw
the universe whole, as we may suppose God sees it, space and time and matter
and evil and all striving and struggling would disappear, and we should
see instead an eternal perfect unchanging spiritual unity.
In this conception, there is undeniably something sublime, something
to which we could wish to yield assent. Nevertheless, when the arguments
in support of it are carefully examined, they appear to involve much confusion
and many unwarrantable assumptions. The fundamental tenet upon which the
system is built up is that what is incomplete must be not self-subsistent,
but must need the support of other things before it can exist. It is held
that whatever has relations to things outside itself must contain some
reference to those outside things in its own nature, and could not,
therefore, be what it is if those outside things did not exist. A man's
nature, for example, is constituted by his memories and the rest of his
knowledge, by his loves and hatreds, and so on; thus, but for the objects
which he knows or loves or hates, he could not be what he is. He is essentially
and obviously a fragment: taken as the sum-total of reality he would be
self-contradictory.
This whole point of view, however, turns upon the notion of the 'nature'
of a thing, which seems to mean 'all the truths about the thing'. It is
of course the case that a truth which connects one thing with another thing
could not subsist if the other thing did not subsist. But a truth about
a thing is not part of the thing itself, although it must, according to
the above usage, be part of the 'nature' of the thing. If we mean by a
thing's 'nature' all the truths about the thing, then plainly we cannot
know a thing's 'nature' unless we know all the thing's relations to all
the other things in the universe. But if the word 'nature' is used in this
sense, we shall have to hold that the thing may be known when its 'nature'
is not known, or at any rate is not known completely. There is a confusion,
when this use of the word 'nature' is employed, between knowledge of things
and knowledge of truths. We may have knowledge of a thing by acquaintance
even if we know very few propositions about it -- theoretically we need
not know any propositions about it. Thus, acquaintance with a thing does
not involve knowledge of its 'nature' in the above sense. And although
acquaintance with a thing is involved in our knowing any one proposition
about a thing, knowledge of its 'nature', in the above sense, is not involved.
Hence, (1) acquaintance with a thing does not logically involve a knowledge
of its relations, and (2) a knowledge of some of its relations does not
involve a knowledge of all of its relations nor a knowledge of its 'nature'
in the above sense. I may be acquainted, for example, with my toothache,
and this knowledge may be as complete as knowledge by acquaintance ever
can be, without knowing all that the dentist (who is not acquainted with
it) can tell me about its cause, and without therefore knowing its 'nature'
in the above sense. Thus the fact that a thing has relations does not prove
that its relations are logically necessary. That is to say, from the mere
fact that it is the thing it is we cannot deduce that it must have the
various relations which in fact it has. This only seems to follow
because we know it already.
It follows that we cannot prove that the universe as a whole forms a
single harmonious system such as Hegel believes that it forms. And if we
cannot prove this, we also cannot prove the unreality of space and time
and matter and evil, for this is deduced by Hegel from the fragmentary
and relational character of these things. Thus we are left to the piecemeal
investigation of the world, and are unable to know the characters of those
parts of the universe that are remote from our experience. This result,
disappointing as it is to those whose hopes have been raised by the systems
of philosophers, is in harmony with the inductive and scientific temper
of our age, and is borne out by the whole examination of human knowledge
which has occupied our previous chapters.
Most of the great ambitious attempts of metaphysicians have proceeded
by the attempt to prove that such and such apparent features of the actual
world were self-contradictory, and therefore could not be real. The whole
tendency of modern thought, however, is more and more in the direction
of showing that the supposed contradictions were illusory, and that very
little can be proved a priori from considerations of what must
be. A good illustration of this is afforded by space and time. Space and
time appear to be infinite in extent, and infinitely divisible. If we travel
along a straight line in either direction, it is difficult to believe that
we shall finally reach a last point, beyond which there is nothing, not
even empty space. Similarly, if in imagination we travel backwards or forwards
in time, it is difficult to believe that we shall reach a first or last
time, with not even empty time beyond it. Thus space and time appear to
be infinite in extent.
Again, if we take any two points on a line, it seems evident that there
must be other points between them, however small the distance between them
may be: every distance can be halved, and the halves can be halved again,
and so on ad infinitum. In time, similarly, however little time
may elapse between two moments, it seems evident that there will be other
moments between them. Thus space and time appear to be infinitely divisible.
But as against these apparent facts -- infinite extent and infinite divisibility
-- philosophers have advanced arguments tending to show that there could
be no infinite collections of things, and that therefore the number of
points in space, or of instants in time, must be finite. Thus a contradiction
emerged between the apparent nature of space and time and the supposed
impossibility of infinite collections.
Kant, who first emphasized this contradiction, deduced the impossibility
of space and time, which he declared to be merely subjective; and since
his time very many philosophers have believed that space and time are mere
appearance, not characteristic of the world as it really is. Now, however,
owing to the labours of the mathematicians, notably Georg Cantor, it has
appeared that the impossibility of infinite collections was a mistake.
They are not in fact self-contradictory, but only contradictory of certain
rather obstinate mental prejudices. Hence the reasons for regarding space
and time as unreal have become inoperative, and one of the great sources
of metaphysical constructions is dried up.
The mathematicians, however, have not been content with showing that
space as it is commonly supposed to be is possible; they have shown also
that many other forms of space are equally possible, so far as logic can
show. Some of Euclid's axioms, which appear to common sense to be necessary,
and were formerly supposed to be necessary by philosophers, are now known
to derive their appearance of necessity from our mere familiarity with
actual space, and not from any a priori logical foundation. By imagining
worlds in which these axioms are false, the mathematicians have used logic
to loosen the prejudices of common sense, and to show the possibility of
spaces differing -- some more, some less -- from that in which we live.
And some of these spaces differ so little from Euclidean space, where distances
such as we can measure are concerned, that it is impossible to discover
by observation whether our actual space is strictly Euclidean or of one
of these other kinds. Thus the position is completely reversed. Formerly
it appeared that experience left only one kind of space to logic, and logic
showed this one kind to be impossible. Now logic presents many kinds of
space as possible apart from experience, and experience only partially
decides between them. Thus, while our knowledge of what is has become less
than it was formerly supposed to be, our knowledge of what may be is enormously
increased. Instead of being shut in within narrow walls, of which every
nook and cranny could be explored, we find ourselves in an open world of
free possibilities, where much remains unknown because there is so much
to know.
What has happened in the case of space and time has happened, to some
extent, in other directions as well. The attempt to prescribe to the universe
by means of a priori principles has broken down; logic instead of
being, as formerly, the bar to possibilities, has become the great liberator
of the imagination, presenting innumerable alternatives which are closed
to unreflective common sense, and leaving to experience the task of deciding,
where decision is possible, between the many worlds which logic offers
for our choice. Thus knowledge as to what exists becomes limited to what
we can learn from experience -- not to what we can actually experience,
for, as we have seen, there is much knowledge by description concerning
things of which we have no direct experience. But in all cases of knowledge
by description, we need some connexion of universals, enabling us, from
such and such a datum, to infer an object of a certain sort as implied
by our datum. Thus in regard to physical objects, for example, the principle
that sense-data are signs of physical objects is itself a connexion of
universals; and it is only in virtue of this principle that experience
enables us to acquire knowledge concerning physical objects. The same applies
to the law of causality, or, to descend to what is less general, to such
principles as the law of gravitation.
Principles such as the law of gravitation are proved, or rather are
rendered highly probable, by a combination of experience with some wholly
a priori principle, such as the principle of induction. Thus our
intuitive knowledge, which is the source of all our other knowledge of
truths, is of two sorts: pure empirical knowledge, which tells us of the
existence and some of the properties of particular things with which we
are acquainted, and pure a priori knowledge, which gives us connexions
between universals, and enables us to draw inferences from the particular
facts given in empirical knowledge. Our derivative knowledge always depends
upon some pure a priori knowledge and usually also depends upon
some pure empirical knowledge.
Philosophical knowledge, if what has been said above is true, does not
differ essentially from scientific knowledge; there is no special source
of wisdom which is open to philosophy but not to science, and the results
obtained by philosophy are not radically different from those obtained
from science. The essential characteristic of philosophy which makes it
a study distinct from science, is criticism. It examines critically
the principles employed in science and in daily life; it searches out any
inconsistencies there may be in these principles, and it only accepts them
when, as the result of a critical inquiry, no reason for rejecting them
has appeared. If, as many philosophers have believed, the principles underlying
the sciences were capable, when disengaged from irrelevant detail, of giving
us knowledge concerning the universe as a whole, such knowledge would have
the same claim on our belief as scientific knowledge has; but our inquiry
has not revealed any such knowledge, and therefore, as regards the special
doctrines of the bolder metaphysicians, has had a mainly negative result.
But as regards what would be commonly accepted as knowledge, our result
is in the main positive: we have seldom found reason to reject such knowledge
as the result of our criticism, and we have seen no reason to suppose man
incapable of the kind of knowledge which he is generally believed to possess.
When, however, we speak of philosophy as a criticism of knowledge,
it is necessary to impose a certain limitation. If we adopt the attitude
of the complete sceptic, placing ourselves wholly outside all knowledge,
and asking, from this outside position, to be compelled to return within
the circle of knowledge, we are demanding what is impossible, and our scepticism
can never be refuted. For all refutation must begin with some piece of
knowledge which the disputants share; from blank doubt, no argument can
begin. Hence the criticism of knowledge which philosophy employs must not
be of this destructive kind, if any result is to be achieved. Against this
absolute scepticism, no logical argument can be advanced. But it
is not difficult to see that scepticism of this kind is unreasonable. Descartes'
'methodical doubt', with which modern philosophy began, is not of this
kind, but is rather the kind of criticism which we are asserting to be
the essence of philosophy. His 'methodical doubt' consisted in doubting
whatever seemed doubtful; in pausing, with each apparent piece of knowledge,
to ask himself whether, on reflection, he could feel certain that he really
knew it. This is the kind of criticism which constitutes philosophy. Some
knowledge, such as knowledge of the existence of our sense-data, appears
quite indubitable, however calmly and thoroughly we reflect upon it. In
regard to such knowledge, philosophical criticism does not require that
we should abstain from belief. But there are beliefs -- such, for example,
as the belief that physical objects exactly resemble our sense-data --
which are entertained until we begin to reflect, but are found to melt
away when subjected to a close inquiry. Such beliefs philosophy will bid
us reject, unless some new line of argument is found to support them. But
to reject the beliefs which do not appear open to any objections, however
closely we examine them, is not reasonable, and is not what philosophy
advocates.
The criticism aimed at, in a word, is not that which, without reason,
determines to reject, but that which considers each piece of apparent knowledge
on its merits, and retains whatever still appears to be knowledge when
this consideration is completed. That some risk of error remains must be
admitted, since human beings are fallible. Philosophy may claim justly
that it diminishes the risk of error, and that in some cases it renders
the risk so small as to be practically negligible. To do more than this
is not possible in a world where mistakes must occur; and more than this
no prudent advocate of philosophy would claim to have performed.
|