|
Bertrand Russell: The Problems of Philosophy

Chapter 10
On Our Knowledge Of Universals
In regard to one man's knowledge at a given time, universals, like particulars,
may be divided into those known by acquaintance, those known only by description,
and those not known either by acquaintance or by description.
Let us consider first the knowledge of universals by acquaintance. It
is obvious, to begin with, that we are acquainted with such universals
as white, red, black, sweet, sour, loud, hard, etc., i.e. with qualities
which are exemplified in sense-data. When we see a white patch, we are
acquainted, in the first instance, with the particular patch; but by seeing
many white patches, we easily learn to abstract the whiteness which they
all have in common, and in learning to do this we are learning to be acquainted
with whiteness. A similar process will make us acquainted with any other
universal of the same sort. Universals of this sort may be called 'sensible
qualities'. They can be apprehended with less effort of abstraction than
any others, and they seem less removed from particulars than other universals
are.
We come next to relations. The easiest relations to apprehend are those
which hold between the different parts of a single complex sense-datum.
For example, I can see at a glance the whole of the page on which I am
writing; thus the whole page is included in one sense-datum. But I perceive
that some parts of the page are to the left of other parts, and some parts
are above other parts. The process of abstraction in this case seems to
proceed somewhat as follows: I see successively a number of sense-data
in which one part is to the left of another; I perceive, as in the case
of different white patches, that all these sense-data have something in
common, and by abstraction I find that what they have in common is a certain
relation between their parts, namely the relation which I call 'being to
the left of'. In this way I become acquainted with the universal relation.
In like manner I become aware of the relation of before and after in
time. Suppose I hear a chime of bells: when the last bell of the chime
sounds, I can retain the whole chime before my mind, and I can perceive
that the earlier bells came before the later ones. Also in memory I perceive
that what I am remembering came before the present time. From either of
these sources I can abstract the universal relation of before and after,
just as I abstracted the universal relation 'being to the left of'. Thus
time-relations, like space-relations, are among those with which we are
acquainted.
Another relation with which we become acquainted in much the same way
is resemblance. If I see simultaneously two shades of green, I can see
that they resemble each other; if I also see a shade of red at the same
time, I can see that the two greens have more resemblance to each other
than either has to the red. In this way I become acquainted with the universal
resemblance or similarity.
Between universals, as between particulars, there relations of which
we may be immediately aware. We have just seen that we can perceive that
the resemblance between two shades of green is greater than the resemblance
between a shade of red and a shade of green. Here we are dealing with a
relation, namely 'greater than', between two relations. Our knowledge of
such relations, though it requires more power of abstraction than is required
for perceiving the qualities of sense-data, appears to be equally immediate,
and (at least in some cases) equally indubitable. Thus there is immediate
knowledge concerning universals well as concerning sense-data.
Returning now to the problem of a priori knowledge, which we
left unsolved when we began the consideration of universals, we find ourselves
in a position to deal with it in a much more satisfactory manner than was
possible before. Let us revert to the proposition 'two and two are four'.
It is fairly obvious, in view of what has been said, that this proposition
states a relation between the universal 'two' and the universal 'four'.
This suggests a proposition which we shall now endeavour to establish:
namely, All a priori knowledge deals exclusively with the relations
of universals. This proposition is of great importance, and goes a
long way towards solving our previous difficulties concerning a priori
knowledge.
The only case in which it might seem, at first sight, as if our proposition
were untrue, is the case in which an a priori proposition states
that all of one class of particulars belong to some other class, or (what
comes the same thing) that all particulars having some one property also
have some other. In this case it might seem as though we were dealing with
the particulars that have the property rather than with the property. The
proposition 'two and two are four' is really a case in point, for this
may be stated in the form 'any two and any other two are four', or 'any
collection formed of two twos is a collection of four'. If we can show
that such statements as this really deal only with universals, our proposition
may be regarded as proved.
One way of discovering what a proposition deals with is to ask ourselves
what words we must understand -- in other words, what objects we must be
acquainted with -- in order to see what the proposition means. As soon
as we see what the proposition means, even if we do not yet know whether
it is true or false, it is evident that we must have acquaintance with
whatever is really dealt with by the proposition. By applying this test,
it appears that many propositions which might seem to be concerned with
particulars are really concerned only with universals. In the special case
of 'two and two are four', even when we interpret it as meaning 'any collection
formed of two twos is a collection of four', it is plain that we can understand
the proposition, i.e. we can see what it is that it asserts, as soon as
we know what is meant by 'collection' and 'two' and 'four' . It is quite
unnecessary to know all the couples in the world: if it were necessary,
obviously we could never understand the proposition, since the couples
are infinitely numerous and therefore cannot all be known to us. Thus although
our general statement implies statements about particular couples,
as soon as we know that there are such particular couples, yet it
does not itself assert or imply that there are such particular couples,
and thus fails to make any statement whatever about actual particular couple.
The statement made is about 'couple', the universal, and not about this
or that couple.
Thus the statement 'two and two are four' deals exclusively with universals,
and therefore may be known by anybody who is acquainted with the universals
concerned and can perceive the relation between them which the statement
asserts. It must be taken as a fact, discovered by reflecting upon our
knowledge, that we have the power of sometimes perceiving such relations
between universals, and therefore of sometimes knowing general a priori
propositions such as those of arithmetic and logic. The thing that seemed
mysterious, when we formerly considered such knowledge, was that it seemed
to anticipate and control experience. This, however, we can now see to
have been an error. No fact concerning anything capable of being
experienced can be known independently of experience. We know a priori
that two things and two other things together make four things, but we
do not know a priori that if Brown and Jones are two, and
Robinson and Smith are two, then Brown and Jones and Robinson and Smith
are four. The reason is that this proposition cannot be understood at all
unless we know that there are such people as Brown and Jones and Robinson
and Smith, and this we can only know by experience. Hence, although our
general proposition is a priori, all its applications to actual
particulars involve experience and therefore contain an empirical element.
In this way what seemed mysterious in our a priori knowledge is
seen to have been based upon an error.
It will serve to make the point dearer if we contrast our genuine a
priori judgement with an empirical generalization, such as 'all men
are mortals'. Here as before, we can understand what the proposition
means as soon as we understand the universals involved, namely man
and mortal. It is obviously unnecessary to have an individual acquaintance
with the whole human race in order to understand what our proposition means.
Thus the difference between an a priori general proposition and
an empirical generalization does not come in the meaning of the
proposition; it comes in the nature of the evidence for it. In the
empirical case, the evidence consists in the particular instances. We believe
that all men are mortal because we know that there are innumerable instances
of men dying, and no instances of their living beyond a certain age. We
do not believe it because we see a connexion between the universal man
and the universal mortal. It is true that if physiology can prove,
assuming the general laws that govern living bodies, that no living organism
can last for ever, that gives a connexion between man and mortality
which would enable us to assert our proposition without appealing to the
special evidence of men dying. But that only means that our generalization
has been subsumed under a wider generalization, for which the evidence
is still of the same kind, though more extensive. The progress of science
is constantly producing such subsumptions, and therefore giving a constantly
wider inductive basis for scientific generalizations. But although this
gives a greater degree of certainty, it does not give a different
kind: the ultimate ground remains inductive, i.e. derived from instances,
and not an a priori connexion of universals such as we have in logic
and arithmetic.
Two opposite points are to be observed concerning a priori general
propositions. The first is that, if many particular instances are known,
our general proposition may be arrived at in the first instance by induction,
and the connexion of universals may be only subsequently perceived. For
example, it is known that if we draw perpendiculars to the sides of a triangle
from the opposite angles, all three perpendiculars meet in a point. It
would be quite possible to be first led to this proposition by actually
drawing perpendiculars in many cases, and finding that they always met
in a point; this experience might lead us to look for the general proof
and find it. Such cases are common in the experience of every mathematician.
The other point is more interesting, and of more philosophical importance.
It is, that we may sometimes know a general proposition in cases where
we do not know a single instance of it. Take such a case as the following:
We know that any two numbers can be multiplied together, and will give
a third called their product. We know that all pairs of integers
the product of which is less than 100 have been actually multiplied together,
and the value of the product recorded in the multiplication table. But
we also know that the number of integers is infinite, and that only a finite
number of pairs of integers ever have been or ever will be thought of by
human beings. Hence it follows that there are pairs of integers which never
have been and never will be thought of by human beings, and that all of
them deal with integers the product of which is over 100. Hence we arrive
at the proposition: 'All products of two integers, which never have been
and never will be thought of by any human being, are over 100.' Here is
a general proposition of which the truth is undeniable, and yet, from the
very nature of the case, we can never give an instance; because any two
numbers we may think of are excluded by the terms of the proposition.
This possibility, of knowledge of general propositions of which no instance
can be given, is often denied, because it is not perceived that the knowledge
of such propositions only requires a knowledge of the relations of universals,
and does not require any knowledge of instances of the universals in question.
Yet the knowledge of such general propositions is quite vital to a great
deal of what is generally admitted to be known. For example, we saw, in
our early chapters, that knowledge of physical objects, as opposed to sense-data,
is only obtained by an inference, and that they are not things with which
we are acquainted. Hence we can never know any proposition of the form
'this is a physical object', where 'this' is something immediately known.
It follows that all our knowledge concerning physical objects is such that
no actual instance can be given. We can give instances of the associated
sense-data, but we cannot give instances of the actual physical objects.
Hence our knowledge as to physical objects depends throughout upon this
possibility of general knowledge where no instance can be given. And the
same applies to our knowledge of other people's minds, or of any other
class of things of which no instance is known to us by acquaintance.
We may now take a survey of the sources of our knowledge, as they have
appeared in the course of our analysis. We have first to distinguish knowledge
of things and knowledge of truths. In each there are two kinds, one immediate
and one derivative. Our immediate knowledge of things, which we called
acquaintance, consists of two sorts, according as the things known
are particulars or universals. Among particulars, we have acquaintance
with sense-data and (probably) with ourselves. Among universals, there
seems to be no principle by which we can decide which can be known by acquaintance,
but it is clear that among those that can be so known are sensible qualities,
relations of space and time, similarity, and certain abstract logical universals.
Our derivative knowledge of things, which we call knowledge by description,
always involves both acquaintance with something and knowledge of truths.
Our immediate knowledge of truths may be called intuitive
knowledge, and the truths so known may be called self-evident truths.
Among such truths are included those which merely state what is given in
sense, and also certain abstract logical and arithmetical principles, and
(though with less certainty) some ethical propositions. Our derivative
knowledge of truths consists of everything that we can deduce from self-evident
truths by the use of self-evident principles of deduction.
If the above account is correct, all our knowledge of truths depends
upon our intuitive knowledge. It therefore becomes important to consider
the nature and scope of intuitive knowledge, in much the same way as, at
an earlier stage, we considered the nature and scope of knowledge by acquaintance.
But knowledge of truths raises a further problem, which does not arise
in regard to knowledge of things, namely the problem of error. Some
of our beliefs turn out to be erroneous, and therefore it becomes necessary
to consider how, if at all, we can distinguish knowledge from error. This
problem does not arise with regard to knowledge by acquaintance, for, whatever
may be the object of acquaintance, even in dreams and hallucinations, there
is no error involved so long as we do not go beyond the immediate object:
error can only arise when we regard the immediate object, i.e. the sense-datum,
as the mark of some physical object. Thus the problems connected with knowledge
of truths are more difficult than those connected with knowledge of things.
As the first of the problems connected with knowledge of truths, let us
examine the nature and scope of our intuitive judgements.
|