|
Bertrand Russell: The Problems of Philosophy

Chapter 11
On Intuitive Knowledge
There is a common impression that everything that we believe ought to
be capable of proof, or at least of being shown to be highly probable.
It is felt by many that a belief for which no reason can be given is an
unreasonable belief. In the main, this view is just. Almost all our common
beliefs are either inferred, or capable of being inferred, from other beliefs
which may be regarded as giving the reason for them. As a rule, the reason
has been forgotten, or has even never been consciously present to our minds.
Few of us ever ask ourselves, for example, what reason there is to suppose
the food we are just going to eat will not turn out to be poison. Yet we
feel, when challenged, that a perfectly good reason could be found, even
if we are not ready with it at the moment. And in this belief we are usually
justified.
But let us imagine some insistent Socrates, who, whatever reason we
give him, continues to demand a reason for the reason. We must sooner or
later, and probably before very long, be driven to a point where we cannot
find any further reason, and where it becomes almost certain that no further
reason is even theoretically discoverable. Starting with the common beliefs
of daily life, we can be driven back from point to point, until we come
to some general principle, or some instance of a general principle, which
seems luminously evident, and is not itself capable of being deduced from
anything more evident. In most questions of daily life, such as whether
our food is likely to be nourishing and not poisonous, we shall be driven
back to the inductive principle, which we discussed in Chapter VI. But
beyond that, there seems to be no further regress. The principle itself
is constantly used in our reasoning, sometimes consciously, sometimes unconsciously;
but there is no reasoning which, starting from some simpler self-evident
principle, leads us to the principle of induction as its conclusion. And
the same holds for other logical principles. Their truth is evident to
us, and we employ them in constructing demonstrations; but they themselves,
or at least some of them, are incapable of demonstration.
Self-evidence, however, is not confined to those among general principles
which are incapable of proof. When a certain number of logical principles
have been admitted, the rest can be deduced from them; but the propositions
deduced are often just as self-evident as those that were assumed without
proof. All arithmetic, moreover, can be deduced from the general principles
of logic, yet the simple propositions of arithmetic, such as 'two and two
are four', are just as self-evident as the principles of logic.
It would seem, also, though this is more disputable, that there are
some self-evident ethical principles, such as 'we ought to pursue what
is good'.
It should be observed that, in all cases of general principles, particular
instances, dealing with familiar things, are more evident than the general
principle. For example, the law of contradiction states that nothing can
both have a certain property and not have it. This is evident as soon as
it is understood, but it is not so evident as that a particular rose which
we see cannot be both red and not red. (It is of course possible that parts
of the rose may be red and parts not red, or that the rose may be of a
shade of pink which we hardly know whether to call red or not; but in the
former case it is plain that the rose as a whole is not red, while in the
latter case the answer is theoretically definite as soon as we have decided
on a precise definition of 'red'.) It is usually through particular instances
that we come to be able to see the general principle. Only those who are
practised in dealing with abstractions can readily grasp a general principle
without the help of instances.
In addition to general principles, the other kind of self-evident truths
are those immediately derived from sensation. We will call such truths
'truths of perception', and the judgements expressing them we will call
'judgements of perception'. But here a certain amount of care is required
in getting at the precise nature of the truths that are self-evident. The
actual sense-data are neither true nor false. A particular patch of colour
which I see, for example, simply exists: it is not the sort of thing that
is true or false. It is true that there is such a patch, true that it has
a certain shape and degree of brightness, true that it is surrounded by
certain other colours. But the patch itself, like everything else in the
world of sense, is of a radically different kind from the things that are
true or false, and therefore cannot properly be said to be true.
Thus whatever self-evident truths may be obtained from our senses must
be different from the sense-data from which they are obtained.
It would seem that there are two kinds of self-evident truths of perception,
though perhaps in the last analysis the two kinds may coalesce. First,
there is the kind which simply asserts the existence of the sense-datum,
without in any way analysing it. We see a patch of red, and we judge 'there
is such-and-such a patch of red', or more strictly 'there is that'; this
is one kind of intuitive judgement of perception. The other kind arises
when the object of sense is complex, and we subject it to some degree of
analysis. If, for instance, we see a round patch of red, we may judge 'that
patch of red is round'. This is again a judgement of perception, but it
differs from our previous kind. In our present kind we have a single sense-datum
which has both colour and shape: the colour is red and the shape is round.
Our judgement analyses the datum into colour and shape, and then recombines
them by stating that the red colour is round in shape. Another example
of this kind of judgement is 'this is to the right of that', where 'this'
and 'that' are seen simultaneously. In this kind of judgement the sense-datum
contains constituents which have some relation to each other, and the judgement
asserts that these constituents have this relation.
Another class of intuitive judgements, analogous to those of sense and
yet quite distinct from them, are judgements of memory. There is
some danger of confusion as to the nature of memory, owing to the fact
that memory of an object is apt to be accompanied by an image of the object,
and yet the image cannot be what constitutes memory. This is easily seen
by merely noticing that the image is in the present, whereas what is remembered
is known to be in the past. Moreover, we are certainly able to some extent
to compare our image with the object remembered, so that we often know,
within somewhat wide limits, how far our image is accurate; but this would
be impossible, unless the object, as opposed to the image, were in some
way before the mind. Thus the essence of memory is not constituted by the
image, but by having immediately before the mind an object which is recognized
as past. But for the fact of memory in this sense, we should not know that
there ever was a past at all, nor should we be able to understand the word
'past', any more than a man born blind can understand the word 'light'.
Thus there must be intuitive judgements of memory, and it is upon them,
ultimately, that all our knowledge of the past depends.
The case of memory, however, raises a difficulty, for it is notoriously
fallacious, and thus throws doubt on the trustworthiness of intuitive judgements
in general. This difficulty is no light one. But let us first narrow its
scope as far as possible. Broadly speaking, memory is trustworthy in proportion
to the vividness of the experience and to its nearness in time. If the
house next door was struck by lightning half a minute ago, my memory of
what I saw and heard will be so reliable that it would be preposterous
to doubt whether there had been a flash at all. And the same applies to
less vivid experiences, so long as they are recent. I am absolutely certain
that half a minute ago I was sitting in the same chair in which I am sitting
now. Going backward over the day, I find things of which I am quite certain,
other things of which I am almost certain, other things of which I can
become certain by thought and by calling up attendant circumstances, and
some things of which I am by no means certain. I am quite certain that
I ate my breakfast this morning, but if I were as indifferent to my breakfast
as a philosopher should be, I should be doubtful. As to the conversation
at breakfast, I can recall some of it easily, some with an effort, some
only with a large element of doubt, and some not at all. Thus there is
a continual gradation in the degree of self-evidence of what I remember,
and a corresponding gradation in the trustworthiness of my memory.
Thus the first answer to the difficulty of fallacious memory is to say
that memory has degrees of self-evidence, and that these correspond to
the degrees of its trustworthiness, reaching a limit of perfect self-evidence
and perfect trustworthiness in our memory of events which are recent and
vivid.
It would seem, however, that there are cases of very firm belief in
a memory which is wholly false. It is probable that, in these cases, what
is really remembered, in the sense of being immediately before the mind,
is something other than what is falsely believed in, though something generally
associated with it. George IV is said to have at last believed that he
was at the battle of Waterloo, because he had so often said that he was.
In this case, what was immediately remembered was his repeated assertion;
the belief in what he was asserting (if it existed) would be produced by
association with the remembered assertion, and would therefore not be a
genuine case of memory. It would seem that cases of fallacious memory can
probably all be dealt with in this way, i.e. they can be shown to be not
cases of memory in the strict sense at all.
One important point about self-evidence is made clear by the case of
memory, and that is, that self-evidence has degrees: it is not a quality
which is simply present or absent, but a quality which may be more or less
present, in gradations ranging from absolute certainty down to an almost
imperceptible faintness. Truths of perception and some of the principles
of logic have the very highest degree of self-evidence; truths of immediate
memory have an almost equally high degree. The inductive principle has
less self-evidence than some of the other principles of logic, such as
'what follows from a true premiss must be true'. Memories have a diminishing
self-evidence as they become remoter and fainter; the truths of logic and
mathematics have (broadly speaking) less self-evidence as they become more
complicated. Judgements of intrinsic ethical or aesthetic value are apt
to have some self-evidence, but not much.
Degrees of self-evidence are important in the theory of knowledge, since,
if propositions may (as seems likely) have some degree of self-evidence
without being true, it will not be necessary to abandon all connexion between
self-evidence and truth, but merely to say that, where there is a conflict,
the more self-evident proposition is to be retained and the less self-evident
rejected.
It seems, however, highly probable that two different notions are combined
in 'self-evidence' as above explained; that one of them, which corresponds
to the highest degree of self-evidence, is really an infallible guarantee
of truth, while the other, which corresponds to all the other degrees,
does not give an infallible guarantee, but only a greater or less presumption.
This, however, is only a suggestion, which we cannot as yet develop further.
After we have dealt with the nature of truth, we shall return to the subject
of self-evidence, in connexion with the distinction between knowledge and
error.
|