|
Bertrand Russell: The Problems of Philosophy

Chapter 8
How A Priori Knowledge Is Possible
Immanuel Kant is generally regarded as the
greatest of the modern philosophers. Though he lived through the Seven Years
War and the French Revolution, he never interrupted his teaching of philosophy
at Konigsberg in East Prussia. His most distinctive contribution was the
invention of what he called the 'critical' philosophy, which, assuming as a
datum that there is knowledge of various kinds, inquired how such knowledge
comes to be possible, and deduced, from the answer to this inquiry, many
metaphysical results as to the nature of the world. Whether these results were
valid may well be doubted. But Kant undoubtedly deserves credit for two things:
first, for having perceived that we have a priori knowledge which is not
purely 'analytic', i.e. such that the opposite would be self-contradictory; and
secondly, for having made evident the philosophical importance of the theory of
knowledge.
Before the time of Kant, it was generally held that whatever knowledge was a
priori must be 'analytic'. What this word means will be best illustrated by
examples. If I say, 'A bald man is a man', 'A plane figure is a figure', 'A bad
poet is a poet', I make a purely analytic judgement: the subject spoken about
is given as having at least two properties, of which one is singled out to be
asserted of it. Such propositions as the above are trivial, and would never be
enunciated in real life except by an orator preparing the way for a piece of
sophistry. They are called 'analytic' because the predicate is obtained by
merely analysing the subject. Before the time of Kant it was thought that all
judgements of which we could be certain a priori were of this kind: that
in all of them there was a predicate which was only part of the subject of
which it was asserted. If this were so, we should be involved in a definite
contradiction if we attempted to deny thinging that could be known a
priori. 'A bald man is not bald' would assert and deny baldness of the same
man, and would therefore contradict itself. Thus according to the philosophers
before Kant, the law of contradiction, which asserts that nothing can at the
same time have and not have a certain property, sufficed to establish the truth
of all a priori knowledge.
Hume (1711-76), who preceded Kant, accepting the usual view as to what makes
knowledge a priori, discovered that, in many cases which had previously
been supposed analytic, and notably in the case of cause and effect, the
connexion was really synthetic. Before Hume, rationalists at least had supposed
that the effect could be logically deduced from the cause, if only we had
sufficient knowledge. Hume argued -- correctly, as would now be generally
admitted -- that this could not be done. Hence he inferred the far more
doubtful proposition that nothing could be known a priori about the
connexion of cause and effect. Kant, who had been educated in the rationalist
tradition, was much perturbed by Hume's scepticism, and endeavoured to find an
answer to it. He perceived that not only the connexion of cause and effect, but
all the propositions of arithmetic and geometry, are 'synthetic' i.e. not
analytic: in all these propositions, no analysis of the subject will reveal the
predicate. His stock instance was the proposition 7 + 5=12. He pointed out,
quite truly, that 7 and 5 have to be put together to give 12: the idea of 12 is
not contained in them, nor even in the idea of adding them together.
Thus he was led to the conclusion that all pure mathematics, though a
priori, is synthetic; and this conclusion raised a new problem of which he
endeavoured to find the solution.
The question which Kant put at the beginning of his philosophy, namely 'How is
pure mathematics possible?' is an interesting and difficult one, to which every
philosophy which is not purely sceptical must find some answer. The answer of
the pure empiricists, that our mathematical knowledge is derived by induction
from particular instances, we have already seen to be inadequate, for two
reasons: first, that the validity of the inductive principle itself cannot be
proved by induction; secondly, that the general propositions of mathematics,
such as 'two and two always make four', can obviously be known with certainty
by consideration of a single instance, and gain nothing by enumeration of other
cases in which they have been found to be true. Thus our knowledge of the
general propositions of mathematics (and the same applies to logic) must be
accounted for otherwise than our (merely probable) knowledge of empirical
generalizations such as 'all men are mortal'.
The problem arises through the fact that such knowledge is general, whereas all
experience is particular. It seems strange that we should apparently be able to
know some truths in advance about particular things of which we have as yet no
experience; but it cannot easily be doubted that logic and arithmetic will
apply to such things. We do not know who will be the inhabitants of London a
hundred years hence; but we know that any two of them and any other two of them
will make four of them. This apparent power of anticipating facts about things
of which we have no experience is certainly surprising. Kant's solution of the
problem, though not valid in my opinion, is interesting. It is, however, very
difficult, and is differently understood by different philosophers. We can,
therefore, only give the merest outline of it, and even that will be thought
misleading by many exponents of Kant's system.
What Kant maintained was that in all our experience there are two elements to
be distinguished, the one due to the object (i.e. to what we have called the
'physical object'), the other due to our own nature. We saw, in discussing
matter and sense-data, that the physical object is different from the
associated sense-data, and that the sense-data are to be regarded as resulting
from an interaction between the physical object and ourselves. So far, we are
in agreement with Kant. But what is distinctive of Kant is the way in which he
apportions the shares of ourselves and the physical object respectively. He
considers that the crude material given in sensation -- the colour, hardness
etc. -- is due to the object, and that what we supply is the arrangement in
space and time, and all the relations between sense-data which result from
comparison or from considering one as the cause of the other or in any other
way. His chief reason in favour of this view is that we seem to have a
priori knowledge as to space and time and causality and comparison, but not
as to the actual crude material of sensation. We can be sure, he says, that
anything we shall ever experience must show the characteristics affirmed of it
in our a priori knowledge, because these characteristics are due to our
own nature, and therefore nothing can ever come into our experience without
acquiring these characteristics.
The physical object, which he calls the 'thing in itself', he regards as
essentially unknowable; what can be known is the object as we have it in
experience, which he calls the 'phenomenon'. The phenomenon, being a joint
product of us and the thing in itself, is sure to have those characteristics
which are due to us, and is therefore sure to conform to our a priori
knowledge. Hence this knowledge, though true of all actual and possible
experience, must not be supposed to apply outside experience. Thus in spite of
the existence of a priori knowledge, we cannot know anything about the
thing in itself or about what is not an actual or possible object of
experience. In this way he tries to reconcile and harmonize the contentions of
the rationalists with the arguments of the empiricists.
Apart from minor grounds on which Kant's philosophy may be criticized, there is
one main objection which seems fatal to any attempt to deal with the problem of
a priori knowledge by his method. The thing to be accounted for is our
certainty that the facts must always conform to logic and arithmetic. To say
that logic and arithmetic are contributed by us does not account for this. Our
nature is as much a fact of the existing world as anything, and there can be no
certainty that it will remain constant. It might happen, if Kant is right, that
to-morrow our nature would so change as to make two and two become five. This
possibility seems never to have occurred to him, yet it is one which utterly
destroys the certainty and universality which he is anxious to vindicate for
arithmetical propositions. It is true that this possibility, formally, is
inconsistent with the Kantian view that time itself is a form imposed by the
subject upon phenomena, so that our real Self is not in time and has no
to-morrow. But he will still have to suppose that the time-order of phenomena
is determined by characteristics of what is behind phenomena, and this suffices
for the substance of our argument.
Reflection, moreover, seems to make it clear that, if there is any truth in our
arithmetical beliefs, they must apply to things equally whether we think of
them or not. Two physical objects and two other physical objects must make four
physical objects, even if physical objects cannot be experienced. To assert
this is certainly within the scope of what we mean when we state that two and
two are four. Its truth is just as indubitable as the truth of the assertion
that two phenomena and two other phenomena make four phenomena. Thus Kant's
solution unduly limits the scope of a priori propositions, in addition
to failing in the attempt at explaining their certainty.
Apart from the special doctrines advocated by Kant, it is very common among
philosophers to regard what is a priori as in some sense mental, as
concerned rather with the way we must think than with any fact of the outer
world. We noted in the preceding chapter the three principles commonly called
'laws of thought'. The view which led to their being so named is a natural one,
but there are strong reasons for thinking that it is erroneous. Let us take as
an illustration the law of contradiction. This is commonly stated in the form
'Nothing can both be and not be', which is intended to express the fact that
nothing can at once have and not have a given quality. Thus, for example, if a
tree is a beech it cannot also be not a beech; if my table is rectangular it
cannot also be not rectangular, and so on.
Now what makes it natural to call this principle a law of thought is
that it is by thought rather than by outward observation that we persuade
ourselves of its necessary truth. When we have seen that a tree is a beech, we
do not need to look again in order to ascertain whether it is also not a beech;
thought alone makes us know that this is impossible. But the conclusion that
the law of contradiction is a law of thought is nevertheless erroneous.
What we believe, when we believe the law of contradiction, is not that the mind
is so made that it must believe the law of contradiction. This belief is
a subsequent result of psychological reflection, which presupposes the belief
in the law of contradiction. The belief in the law of contradiction is a belief
about things, not only about thoughts. It is not, e.g., the belief that if we
think a certain tree is a beech, we cannot at the same time think
that it is not a beech; it is the belief that if a tree is a beech, it
cannot at the same time be not a beech. Thus the law of contradiction is
about things, and not merely about thoughts; and although belief in the law of
contradiction is a thought, the law of contradiction itself is not a thought,
but a fact concerning the things in the world. If this, which we believe when
we believe the law of contradiction, were not true of the things in the world,
the fact that we were compelled to think it true would not save the law
of contradiction from being false; and this shows that the law is not a law of
thought.
A similar argument applies to any other a priori judgement. When we
judge that two and two are four, we are not making a judgement about our
thoughts, but about all actual or possible couples. The fact that our minds are
so constituted as to believe that two and two are four, though it is true, is
emphatically not what we assert when we assert that two and two are four. And
no fact about the constitution of our minds could make it true that two
and two are four. Thus our a priori knowledge, if it is not erroneous,
is not merely knowledge about the constitution of our minds, but is applicable
to whatever the world may contain, both what is mental and what is non-mental.
The fact seems to be that all our a priori knowledge is concerned with
entities which do not, properly speaking exist, either in the mental or
in the physical world. These entities are such as can be named by parts of
speech which are not substantives; they are such entities as qualities and
relations. Suppose, for instance, that I am in my room. I exist, and my room
exists; but does 'in' exist? Yet obviously the word 'in' has a meaning; it
denotes a relation which holds between me and my room. This relation is
something, although we cannot say that it exists in the same sense in
which I and my room exist. The relation 'in' is something which we can think
about and understand, for, if we could not understand it, we could not
understand the sentence 'I am in my room'. Many philosophers, following Kant,
have maintained that relations are the work of the mind, that things in
themselves have no relations, but that the mind brings them together in one act
of thought and thus produces the relations which it judges them to have.
This view, however, seems open to objections similar to those which we urged
before against Kant. It seems plain that it is not thought which produces the
truth of the proposition 'I am in my room'. It may be true that an earwig is in
my room, even if neither I nor the earwig nor any one else is aware of this
truth; for this truth concerns only the earwig and the room, and does not
depend upon anything else. Thus relations, as we shall see more fully in the
next chapter, must be placed in a world which is neither mental nor physical.
This world is of great importance to philosophy, and in particular to the
problems of a priori knowledge. In the next chapter we shall proceed to
develop its nature and its bearing upon the questions with which we have been
dealing.
Kant's 'thing in itself' is identical in definition with the
physical object, namely, it is the cause of sensations. In the properties
deduced from the definition it is not identical, since Kant held (in spite of
some inconsistency as regards cause) that we can know that none of the
categories are applicable to the 'thing in itself'. |